John Stuart Mill
"Speech In Favor of Capital Punishment"
About the Article: This speech was given before Parliament on April 21, 1868 in opposition to a bill banning capital punishment that had been proposed by Mr. Gilpin.
. . . It would be a great
satisfaction to me if I were able to support this Motion. It is always a matter
of regret to me to find myself, on a public question, opposed to those who are
called--sometimes in the way of honour, and sometimes in what is intended for
ridicule--the philanthropists. Of all persons who take part in public affairs,
they are those for whom, on the whole, I feel the greatest amount of respect;
for their characteristic is, that they devote their time, their labour, and
much of their money to objects purely public, with a less admixture of either
personal or class selfishness, than any other class of politicians whatever. On
almost all the great questions, scarcely any politicians are so steadily and
almost uniformly to be found on the side of right; and they seldom err, but by
an exaggerated application of some just and highly important principle. On the
very subject that is now occupying us we all know what signal service they have
rendered. It is through their efforts that our criminal laws--which within my
memory hanged people for stealing in a dwelling house to the value of 40s.-laws
by virtue of which rows of human beings might be seen suspended in front of
Newgate by those who ascended or descended Ludgate Hill--have so greatly
relaxed their most revolting and most impolitic ferocity, that aggravated
murder is now practically the only crime which is punished with death by any of
our lawful tribunals; and we are even now deliberating whether the extreme
penalty should be retained in that solitary case. This vast gain, not only to
humanity, but to the ends of penal justice, we owe to the philanthropists; and
if they are mistaken, as I cannot but think they are, in the present instance,
it is only in not perceiving the right time and place for stopping in a career
hitherto so eminently beneficial. Sir, there is a point at which, I conceive,
that career ought to stop. When there has been brought home to any one, by
conclusive evidence, the greatest crime known to the law; and when the
attendant circumstances suggest no palliation of the guilt, no hope that the
culprit may even yet not be unworthy to live among mankind, nothing to make it
probable that the crime was an exception to his general character rather than a
consequence of it, then I confess it appears to me that to deprive the criminal
of the life of which he has proved himself to be unworthy--solemnly to blot him
out from the fellowship of mankind and from the catalogue of the living--is the
most appropriate as it is certainly the most impressive, mode in which society
can attach to so great a crime the penal consequences which for the security of
life it is indispensable to annex to it. I defend this penalty, when
confined to atrocious cases, on the very ground on which it is commonly
attacked--on that of humanity to the criminal; as beyond comparison the
least cruel mode in which it is possible adequately to deter from the crime.
If, in our horror of inflicting death, we endeavour to devise some punishment
for the living criminal which shall act on the human mind with a deterrent
force at all comparable to that of death, we are driven to inflictions less
severe indeed in appearance, and therefore less efficacious, but far more cruel
in reality. Few, I think, would venture to propose, as a punishment for
aggravated murder, less than imprisonment with hard labor for life; that is the
fate to which a murderer would be consigned by the mercy which shrinks from
putting him to death. But has it been sufficiently considered what sort of a
mercy this is, and what kind of life it leaves to him? If, indeed, the
punishment is not really inflicted--if it becomes the sham which a few years
ago such punishments were rapidly becoming--then, indeed, its adoption would be
almost tantamount to giving up the attempt to repress murder altogether. But if
it really is what it professes to be, and if it is realized in all its rigour
by the popular imagination, as it very probably would not be, but as it must be
if it is to be efficacious, it will be so shocking that when the memory of the
crime is no longer fresh, there will be almost insuperable difficulty in
executing it. What comparison can there really be, in point of severity,
between consigning a man to the short pang of a rapid death, and immuring him
in a living tomb, there to linger out what may be a long life in the hardest
and most monotonous toil, without any of its alleviations or rewards--debarred from
all pleasant sights and sounds, and cut off from all earthly hope, except a
slight mitigation of bodily restraint, or a small improvement of diet? Yet even
such a lot as this, because there is no one moment at which the suffering is of
terrifying intensity, and, above all, because it does not contain the element,
so imposing to the imagination, of the unknown, is universally reputed a milder
punishment than death--stands in all codes as a mitigation of the capital
penalty, and is thankfully accepted as such. For it is characteristic of all
punishments which depend on duration for their efficacy--all, therefore, which
are not corporal or pecuniary--that they are more rigorous than they seem;
while it is, on the contrary, one of the strongest recommendations a punishment
can have, that it should seem more rigorous than it is; for its practical
power depends far less on what it is than on what it seems. There is not, I
should think, any human infliction which makes an impression on the imagination
so entirely out of proportion to its real severity as the punishment of death. The
punishment must be mild indeed which does not add more to the sum of human
misery than is necessarily or directly added by the execution of a criminal. As
my hon. Friend the Member for Northampton (Mr.Gilpin) has himself remarked, the
most that human laws can do to anyone in the matter of death is to hasten it;
the man would have died at any rate; not so very much later, and on the
average, I fear, with a considerably greater amount of bodily suffering. Society
is asked, then, to denude itself of an instrument of punishment which, in the
grave cases to which alone it is suitable, effects its purposes at a less cost
of human suffering than any other; which, while it inspires more terror, is
less cruel in actual fact than any punishment that we should think of
substituting for it. My hon. Friend says that it does not inspire terror, and
that experience proves it to be a failure. But the influence of a punishment is
not to be estimated by its effect on hardened criminals. Those whose habitual
way of life keeps them, so to speak, at all times within sight of the gallows,
do grow to care less about it; as, to compare good things with bad, an old
soldier is not much affected by the chance of dying in battle. I can afford to
admit all that is often said about the indifference of professional criminals
to the gallows. Though of that indifference one-third is probably bravado and
another third confidence that they shall have the luck to escape, it is quite
probable that the remaining third is real. But the efficacy of a punishment
which acts principally through the imagination, is chiefly to be measured by
the impression it makes on those who are still innocent; by the horror with
which it surrounds the first promptings of guilt; the restraining influence it
exercises over the beginning of the thought which, if indulged, would become a
temptation; the check which it exerts over the graded declension towards the
state--never suddenly attained--in which crime no longer revolts, and
punishment no longer terrifies. As for what is called the failure of death
punishment, who is able to judge of that? We partly know who those are whom it
has not deterred; but who is there who knows whom it has deterred, or how many
human beings it has saved who would have lived to be murderers if that awful
association had not been thrown round the idea of murder from their earliest
infancy? Let us not forget that the most imposing fact loses its power over the
imagination if it is made too cheap. When a punishment fit only for the most
atrocious crimes is lavished on small offences until human feeling recoils from
it, then, indeed, it ceases to intimidate, because it ceases to be believed in.
The failure of capital punishment in cases of theft is easily accounted for;
the thief did not believe that it would be inflicted. He had learnt by
experience that jurors would perjure themselves rather than find him guilty;
that Judges would seize any excuse for not sentencing him to death, or for
recommending him to mercy; and that if neither jurors nor Judges were merciful,
there were still hopes from an authority above both. When things had come to
this pass it was high time to give up the vain attempt. When it is impossible
to inflict a punishment, or when its infliction becomes a public scandal, the
idle threat cannot too soon disappear from the statute book. And in the case of
the host of offences which were formerly capital, I heartily rejoice that it
did become impracticable to execute the law. If the same state of public
feeling comes to exist in the case of murder; if the time comes when jurors
refuse to find a murderer guilty; when Judges will not sentence him to death,
or will recommend him to mercy; or when, if juries and Judges do not flinch
from their duty, Home Secretaries, under pressure of deputations and memorials,
shrink from theirs, and the threat becomes, as it became in the other cases, a
mere brutum fulmen; then, indeed, it may become necessary to do in this
case what has been done in those--to abrogate the penalty. That time may
come--my hon. Friend thinks that it has nearly come. I hardly know whether he
lamented it or boasted of it; but he and his Friends are entitled to the boast;
for if it comes it will be their doing, and they will have gained what I cannot
but call a fatal victory, for they will have achieved it by bringing about, if
they will forgive me for saying so, an enervation, an effeminancy, in the
general mind of the country. For what else than effeminancy is it to be so much
more shocked by taking a man's life than by depriving him of all that makes
life desirable or valuable? Is death, then, the greatest of all earthly ills? Usque
adeone mori miserum est? Is it, indeed, so dreadful a thing to die? Has it
not been from of old one chief part of a manly education to make us despise
death--teaching us to account it, if an evil at all, by no means high in the
list of evils; at all events, as an inevitable one, and to hold, as it were,
our lives in our hands, ready to be given or risked at any moment, for a
sufficiently worthy object? I am sure that my hon. Friends know all this as
well, and have as much of all these feelings as any of the rest of us; possibly
more. But I cannot think that this is likely to be the effect of their teaching
on the general mind. I cannot think that the cultivating of a peculiar
sensitiveness of conscience on this one point, over and above what results from
the general cultivation of the moral sentiments, is permanently consistent with
assigning in our own minds to the fact of death no more than the degree of
relative importance which belongs to it among the other incidents of our
humanity. The men of old cared too little about death, and gave their own lives
or took those of others with equal recklessness. Our danger is of the opposite
kind, lest we should be so much shocked by death, in general and in the
abstract, as to care too much about it in individual cases, both those of other
people and our own, which call for its being risked. And I am not putting
things at the worst, for it is proved by the experience of other countries that
horror of the executioner by no means necessarily implies horror of the
assassin. The stronghold, as we all know, of hired assassination in the 18th century
was Italy; yet it is said that in some of the Italian populations the
infliction of death by sentence of law was in the highest degree offensive and
revolting to popular feeling. Much has been said of the sanctity of human life,
and the absurdity of supposing that we can teach respect for life by ourselves
destroying it. But I am surprised at the employment of this argument, for it is
one which might be brought against any punishment whatever. It is not human
life only, not human life as such, that ought to be sacred to us, but human
feelings. The human capacity of suffering is what we should cause to be
respected, not the mere capacity of existing. And we may imagine somebody
asking how we can teach people not to inflict suffering by ourselves inflicting
it? But to this I should answer--all of us would answer--that to deter by
suffering from inflicting suffering is not only possible, but the very purpose
of penal justice. Does fining a criminal show want of respect for property, or
imprisoning him, for personal freedom? Just as unreasonable is it to think that
to take the life of a man who has taken that of another is to show want of
regard for human life. We show, on the contrary, most emphatically our regard
for it, by the adoption of a rule that he who violates that right in another
forfeits it for himself, and that while no other crime that he can commit
deprives him of his right to live, this shall. There is one argument against
capital punishment, even in extreme cases, which I cannot deny to have
weight--on which my hon. Friend justly laid great stress, and which never can
be entirely got rid of. It is this--that if by an error of justice an innocent
person is put to death, the mistake can never be corrected; all compensation,
all reparation for the wrong is impossible. This would be indeed a serious
objection if these miserable mistakes--among the most tragical occurrences in
the whole round of human affairs--could not be made extremely rare. The
argument is invincible where the mode of criminal procedure is dangerous to the
innocent, or where the Courts of Justice are not trusted. And this probably is
the reason why the objection to an irreparable punishment began (as I believe
it did) earlier, and is more intense and more widely diffused, in some parts of
the Continent of Europe than it is here. There are on the Continent great and
enlightened countries, in which the criminal procedure is not so favorable to
innocence, does not afford the same security against erroneous conviction, as
it does among us; countries where the Courts of Justice seem to think they fail
in their duty unless they find somebody guilty; and in their really laudable
desire to hunt guilt from its hiding places, expose themselves to a serious
danger of condemning the innocent. If our own procedure and Courts of Justice
afforded ground for similar apprehension, I should be the first to join in
withdrawing the power of inflicting irreparable punishment from such tribunals.
But we all know that the defects of our procedure are the very opposite. Our
rules of evidence are even too favorable to the prisoner; and juries and Judges
carry out the maxim, "It is better that ten guilty should escape than that
one innocent person should suffer," not only to the letter, but beyond the
letter. Judges are most anxious to point out, and juries to allow for, the
barest possibility of the prisoner's innocence. No human judgment is
infallible; such sad cases as my hon. Friend cited will sometimes occur; but in
so grave a case as that of murder, the accused, in our system, has always the
benefit of the merest shadow of a doubt. And this suggests another
consideration very germane to the question. The very fact that death punishment
is more shocking than any other to the imagination, necessarily renders the
Courts of Justice more scrupulous in requiring the fullest evidence of guilt. Even
that which is the greatest objection to capital punishment, the impossibility
of correcting an error once committed, must make, and does make, juries and
Judges more careful in forming their opinion, and more jealous in their
scrutiny of the evidence. If the substitution of penal servitude for death in
cases of murder should cause any declaration in this conscientious
scrupulosity, there would be a great evil to set against the real, but I hope
rare, advantage of being able to make reparation to a condemned person who was
afterwards discovered to be innocent. In order that the possibility of
correction may be kept open wherever the chance of this sad contingency is more
than infinitesimal, it is quite right that the Judge should recommend to the
Crown a commutation of the sentence, not solely when the proof of guilt is open
to the smallest suspicion, but whenever there remains anything unexplained and
mysterious in the case, raising a desire for more light, or making it likely
that further information may at some future time be obtained. I would also
suggest that whenever the sentence is commuted the grounds of the commutation
should, in some authentic form, be made known to the public. Thus much I
willingly concede to my hon. Friend; but on the question of total abolition I
am inclined to hope that the feeling of the country is not with him, and that
the limitation of death punishment to the cases referred to in the Bill of last
year will be generally considered sufficient. The mania which existed a short
time ago for paring down all our punishments seems to have reached its limits,
and not before it was time. We were in danger of being left without any
effectual punishment, except for small of offences. What was formerly our chief
secondary punishment--transportation--before it was abolished, had become
almost a reward. Penal servitude, the substitute for it, was becoming, to the
classes who were principally subject to it, almost nominal, so comfortable did
we make our prisons, and so easy had it become to get quickly out of them. Flogging--a
most objectionable punishment in ordinary cases, but a particularly appropriate
one for crimes of brutality, especially crimes against women--we would not hear
of, except, to be sure, in the case of garotters, for whose peculiar benefit we
reestablished it in a hurry, immediately after a Member of Parliament had been
garrotted. With this exception, offences, even of an atrocious kind, against
the person, as my hon. and learned Friend the Member for Oxford (Mr.Neate) well
remarked, not only were, but still are, visited with penalties so ludicrously
inadequate, as to be almost an encouragement to the crime. I think, Sir, that
in the case of most offences, except those against property, there is more need
of strengthening our punishments than of weakening them; and that severer
sentences, with an apportionment of them to the different kinds of offences
which shall approve itself better than at present to the moral sentiments of
the community, are the kind of reform of which our penal system now stands in
need. I shall therefore vote against the Amendment.